Northern Ireland's community philosophy blog, administered by philosophers at Queen's University Belfast on behalf of the Belfast Branch of the Royal Institute of Philosophy
Monday, 27 February 2012
Laughing at Life
Friday, 24 February 2012
Friday Question: On the Evidential Argument from Evil
(1) If there were a God, there would be no gratuitous evils (GEs)
(2) It is probable that at least one of the evils in our world is a GE.
(3) Therefore: probably, there is no God.
Firstly, regarding GEs: A given evil is a gratuitious evil (GE) if it is such that God would have no adequate justifying reason for permitting it (e.g. there is no sufficiently outweighing good that could not have been brought about without permitting a particular evil). [For more on gratuitous evil, see here].
In support of premise (2), William Rowe has suggested that mere reflection on some of the more heinous forms of evil in our world ought to convince us that it is probable that at least one of the evils in our world is a GE. As Murray and Rea suggest, "It seems simply obvious when we consider cases like [<Warning: distressing picture> a deer dying an agonizing, slow death in a forest fire] that there is no greater good to which we might appeal that could justify it." (Murray and Rea 2008: 167). Stephen Wykstra calls these kind of arguments "Noseeum Arguments": when considering certain cases like that of the deer, we look long and hard for some possible greater good, and yet we come up empty handed; put simply: we can't see any possible greater good, so it's probably not there.
As Murray and Rea point out, two conditions have to be met for a Noseeum inference to be a good one. Firstly, you have to be looking for the thing in question in the right place. Secondly, it must be the case that you would see the thing in question if it were really there. A Noseeum inference is a poor one if either of these conditions isn't met. After all, your inference that there is no milk in the refrigerator is no good if either (i) you would know milk if you saw it but looked in the wrong place for it (say, the garage), or, (ii) you looked in the right place for it (the fridge) but wouldn't know it if you saw it (say, you think milk looks like something much different than it does). Skeptical theists object to Noseeum arguments in defence of (2) of the Direct Argument, and this is because they think we are not well positioned when it comes to identifying assessing the reasons God might have for permitting evil. Their main contentions here are that, given the finitude of our human cognitive and moral faculties, it seems that there are many types of good with which we are not familiar, and further, that even if we were acquainted with the relevant goods, there is doubt that we would adequately comprehend the role these evils might play in bringing about those goods. (Murray & Rea 169.) Rowe responds to Skeptical Theists on this point by suggesting that, a problematic implication of their position is that we we must admit that no matter how much evil there might be in the world (and no matter how terrible it seems) we would never be in a position to accept (2): that it is probable that at least one of the evils in the world is a GE. Rowe also suggests that, in reply to the Skeptical Theists, it's not just that we looked and we can't see reasons that might justify God in permitting certain heinous evils (i.e. the deer's agonizing death), but that we can't even conceive of what such reasons would be. What do you think of Rowe's replies to the Skeptical Theist at this juncture? How might the Skeptical Theist reply?
Wednesday, 22 February 2012
Is New Atheism philosophically interesting?
Tuesday, 21 February 2012
Royal Institute of Philosophy Public Lecture
This event, which is part of the Royal Institute of Philosophy Public Lecture series, is open to everyone, and undergraduate and graduate students are particularly welcome to attend.
Sunday, 19 February 2012
A Puzzle About Compensation
Duties of rectification are a familiar part of practical reasoning. Both as a matter of law and morality, it seems only right and proper that wrongdoers ought to try to set matters straight by providing full and adequate reparation. But what qualifies as full and adequate reparation? Accepting for the sake of argument that there are duties of rectification, what counts as fulfilling them?
One approach to this question appeals to the Counterfactual Test. This holds that the duty of rectification is a duty to establish the situation that would have obtained had the initial wrong not taken place. On this view, if I wrong you with the result that you end up on n units of utility, but you would have ended up on n+1 units of utility had I not wronged you, then I fully discharge my duty of rectification if I bring your utility-level up from n to n+1.
However, this account of what it means to provide “full and adequate reparation” encounters a curious problem in cases where a wrongful injury is followed by an unexpected benefit. Suppose, for example, that I wilfully damage your car, with the result that you miss your flight to America, but it so happens that the flight in question crashes into the Atlantic, with the loss of life of everyone on board. The Counterfactual Test implies that I fully rectify the wrong by bringing about the situation that would have obtained had I not damaged your car, which in this instance involves your dying in a plane crash. But clearly this is absurd: rectifying my wrong can’t involve my killing you.
I therefore wonder whether there is a way of characterizing “full and adequate reparation” which is plausible in its own right and which handles cases of “unexpected benefit” in a satisfactory way. One option, of course, is to insist that, in the plane crash case, no wrong has been committed and no duty of rectification has been incurred. Another option is to tweak the Counterfactual Test so that the relevant point of comparison isn’t the (near) possible world where you die in the plane crash but the (more distant) possible world in which you catch the flight and cross the Atlantic safely. But can either of these options be made to work? Or should we search for a different strategy for thinking about rectification that does away with counterfactual reasoning altogether? What do readers think?
Friday, 17 February 2012
Annual Spring Conference of the IPS: Philosophy in Ireland
--
Rev. Dr Gavan Jennings
Hon. Sec. IPS
t: 353 (0)1 6767 420
m: 086 065 2313info@irishphilosophicalsociety.ie
gavanjennings@gmail.com
The Irish Philosophical Society
Cumann Fealsúnachta na hÉireann
Tuesday, 14 February 2012
Blog: New Spring Semester Schedule
Mondays: Post by a QUB Philosophy staff member.
Wednesdays: Post by a member of the QUB Philosophy Society
Fridays: Friday Question (Sometimes this will be written by a staff member, sometimes by a student from Dr. Jarvis's Human Nature module.
I want to thank Patrick Campbell for his work in helping to organize the Wednesday slot and Dr. Jarvis for taking the initiative with his class for various Friday Questions.
In the near future, we can expect Monday staff posts from Dr. Morrison, Dr. Watkins, Dr. Kerr, and Dr. Blease.
Additionally, as was updated earlier, there will be more Philosophy news posted here as well as information about local events (conferences, workshops, etc.).
Looking forward to a great semester of philosophical blogging, Dr. Carter
Monday, 13 February 2012
Relations and Explanations
One of the odd (and intriguing) features about beliefs and desires, however, is that having them seems to be partly a matter of having certain relational properties. For instance, a person's believing that Obama is the president of the US depends on their standing in the right kind of relationship to Obama. This is not a relationship that Julius Caesar stood in with respect to Obama; Julius Caesar could not have beliefs about Obama in the way that we can.
However, once we realize that having beliefs and desires involves having these relational properties, it is not clear why they should be important in explaining behavior. Relational properties are, in many instances, not very interesting for these kinds of explanatory purposes. For instance, it can appear bizarre, upon reflection, why standing in certain relations with the stars should make any difference to a person's earthly behavior, activities, encounters, situations, etc. That's at least part of what's strange about the suggestions of astrologists.
Consequently, there is a serious question as to whether beliefs and desires are themselves explanatory, or, for instance, whether having beliefs and desires merely entails that one is in other states that explain behavior. Thoughts?
Friday, 10 February 2012
Friday question: The possibility of an eternally created universe
So, to finish with a question, I would like to ask: is there any way of justifying the principle, often assumed in these discussions, that what does not have a beginning does not have a cause?
Sunday, 5 February 2012
Open-mindedness and Intellectual Virtue
What makes open-mindedness, so construed, an intellectual virtue? What makes it an intellectual, rather than a moral, virtue is its motivational component. Even though it need not track the truth, it is characterized by a motivation for truth. What makes it a virtue, rather than a skill or a habit of some other sort? It is a virtue partly because it is an entrenched habit that expresses the agent’s epistemic values.[35] The morally just person wants to respect the rights of others appropriately because she wants what appears good and believes that respecting the rights of others appropriately is good. In this manner, the motivational component of justice expresses her moral values. Analogously, the open-minded person wants to listen to others’ ideas that are thought to be true because she wants the truth and thinks that she can attain it by listening to those ideas. Moreover, she wants the truth because it appears good from an epistemic point of view. Accordingly, the motivational component of open-mindedness expresses her epistemic values.Is this plausible? If so, should we think that what makes any trait an intellectual virtue has something to do with one's motivation and nothing to do with reliably achieving the truth? One problem here is that a motivationalist picture would seem to exclude a plausible explanation for why faculty virtues (i.e. good memory) constitute intellectual virtues. Faculty virtues, as Sosa and Greco note, aid us epistemically by reliably getting us to the truth, and involve no obvious motivational element.
It seems that reflecting on openmindedness presents three options for the virtue epistemologist. First, maintain that reliability is a necessary ingredient of intellectual virtue and explain (contra Battaly and Montmarquet) how the epistemic value of openmindedness lies primarily in its reliability. Secondly, deny that openmindeness is an intellectual virtue because it reliably brings about the truth, and insist that it is so rather because it involves a virtuous motivation for truth, and then defend a motivationalist account of intellectual virtue more broadly. Thirdly, one might reject the EVM picture in favour of a pluralist account of fundamental epistemic value and explain why openmindedness is an intellectual virtue by way of its connection to some fundamental epistemic value other than truth. Which, if any, of these avenues is most plausible?
Wednesday, 1 February 2012
Undergraduate Philosophy Conference (Liverpool)
Details
To all philosophers! We are pleased to announce that the University of Liverpool Philosophy Society will be holding its first Undergraduate Philosophy Conference next March. Submissions are welcome from anyone with current undergraduate status or equivalent.
Your papers can be on any topic you wish, from analytic discussion to continental enquiry, and any branch of philosophy. This is an opportunity to pursue your own interests in philosophy and we are hoping for a wide variety of topics. Please note that the papers should be clearly written, argumentative and demonstrate some original thinking, not merely descriptive or a simple regurgitation of a particular philosopher's work. The required length is 3000-5000 words to ensure at least 20-30 mins presenting time.
If your paper is accepted, all expenses except travel will be covered by the conference.
Please submit your papers to H.E.Lewendon-Evans@student.liverpool.ac.uk. For each paper, please attach a cover letter that includes an abstract of the paper, your name, institution and email address. The submission deadline is midnight of Friday 10th February 2012.
For more information, see here .